"Historical questions are always monographic, either because of the limited manner in which the subject is conceived or because of the specialization of treatment. For history this is indeed necessary, since the academic division of labour imposes certain limitations. But when the empirical investigator glories in his refusal to go beyond the specialized observation dictated by the traditions of his discipline, be they ever so inclusive, he is making a virtue out of a defense mechanism which insures him against questioning his presuppositions."
Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia. p 90.
Sunday, May 10, 2015
Friday, May 1, 2015
Paul Lapie. "La justice pénale"
A colleague recently pointed me to a short essay, “La justice pénale,” by Paul Lapie in the Revue de métaphysique et de morale. It’s from the March 1898 issue of the journal
and this colleague came across it because the Union pour l’action morale reprinted and distributed it. Lapie, and
the Rmm, have figured in my work
before. So I read with interest and finally could no resist writing a little
bit about it.
The essay, only about 12 pages long, might at first look like a book review, although it appears in the “Questions pratiques” rubric.
At its head we find a book listing: Jean Cruppi, La cour d’assises, but also “La collection des journaux française,
depuis six mois.” Many of Céléstin Bouglé’s essays from this period had similar
notices, but I’m not sure how common the practice was. Especially in Bouglé’s
case, the notices are clearly intended for the curious reader, but also as sign
of scholarship, a bibliography even in the field of what was never really
admitted to be polemic. In other words: I may be writing about contemporary
political matters, but I’m a scholar not just some scribbler. It’s hard,
though, not to smile at Lapie’s breezy ‘the papers in the last six months...’
In any case, the essay is divided into two parts—institutions
et croyances—and the first draws directly (or so it appears) on Cruppi to
present practical issues in this particular part of the French legal system,
arguing that the vices of the civilian courts are magnified in the military
ones. I’m not prepared to adjudicate in any useful way these claims. But a few
points. First of all, the judges are not really impartial, because they are
associated so closely with the prosecutors. We needn’t be thought simply to be
copying the English system, Lapie says, if we simply want to bring a bit more
independence and institutional separation to the judge (265). Judges also
simply do not have the time to think about cases in a meaningful way. Lapie
quotes Cruppi telling us that some judges are obliged to rule on as many as a
hundred cases a day (262). Absurd. To judge, after all, is complex. “Les faits
établis, ils [les juges] sauront appliquer les lois. Mais comment les faits
sont-ils établis?” (261). Even the
question of what happened is not so straightforward, “l’accusé est-il l’auteur
du fait incriminé?” is one question, another is “l’accusé est-il responsable de
son acte?” (262) Finally is correct application of the law. Thus there are
three questions, the first is essentially historical, the second moral, and the
third juridical. One needs both time and method—science—even and perhaps
especially for moral problems.
And here is Lapie’s great theme. Given the current state of
affairs, judges and juries have no choice but to fall back on “la conscience.”
Since in this format I can, here is a
large block quote:

(263)
Among the things I wish I understood a bit better is the
claim here about the yes-or-no nature of the judgment. Is this really the case?
And I am a little amazed at the link between the historian and the judge. How
common was this comparison at the time? (It’s history, not historiography
that is supposed to be the Weltgericht).
But it’s really the necessity of falling back on ‘intimate conviction’ that
Lapie finds objectionable. He admits that judges have no choice: “la méthode
qu’on les contraint de suivre les supent [sic?] dans le vide.” They are obliged
to fall back on experience guided by intuition to make rapid decisions. This is
not acceptable. Lapie raises the practice of indicating doubt as to true guilt
with lighter sentences as an especially outrageous byproduct of the
situation.
In the case of military justice, the situation is even
worse. Without impugning the honor or rectitude of the officers concerned, it
is still necessary to point out, Lapie says, that here there is hardly any of
the juridical learning that, at least, civilian judges have. “Nous retrouvons
donc dans la justice militaire, aggravés par l’incompétence, les vices de notre
justice pénale.” Conscience is invoked especially often within the military.
(265)
Especially that last line! And this is in March of 1898.
Zola had been convicted for libel only the month before—not, of course, that
the name “Dreyfus” appears anywhere in this piece. Indeed the above is one of
the more direct references to what Lapie also refers to later on as “the
present crisis,” with no modifiers.
Since any citizen might be obliged to sit on a jury, why not
bring some measure of juridical education into the curriculum? This is not,
Lapie hastens to add, to say that we should teach everyone law, only “tous
devraient avoir acquis le goût et l’habitude de la recherche méthodique” (266).
Here, again, the historian is the model. We demand more evidence of “esprit
critique” in the historian reconstructing “les faits et gestes de Clovis” than
of judges, and this is wrong. This plea for education makes Lapie transition to
the second part of the essay, which looks at the underlying cause for the
institutional problems, which Lapie sees in “croyances...la survivance d’anciens
préjugés” (266). I’ll point out, given this straightforward refusal of
sociology, that the first article in the very next issue of the Rmm is Durkheim’s “Représentations
individuelles et représentations collectives.”
Two contrasting pairs of terms dominate the second half of
the essay: justice and order, as a pair of governing principles, and then
conscience and science. We claim today, following the Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen, says Lapie, to
prioritize justice. But it is easy to see that most people—a legacy of
empire?—prefer order. The appeal to conscience is simply another form of the
religious mindset. Yet it remains widespread in “une sorte de kantisme
instinctif d’après lequel il suffit d’obéir à sa conscience pour faire le bien”
(268). And we should vigorously refuse the idea that balance must be struck
between order and justice. Of course, the government is charged with
maintaining order. But we must not be hypnotized by the old regime: “la justice
n’était jadis qu’un moyen de maintenir l’ordre; l’ordre ne doit être maintenant
qu’un moyen de garantir la justice” (268). For we inhabitants of the 21st
century, this remains an attractive formulation. But Lapie’s counter-intuitive
move is to firmly reject the appeal to conscience in just this context. To have
the “intimate conviction” that you have done your duty is almost completely
worthless. Some lines from one extraordinary paragraph: “La conscience n’est
souveraine que si elle est éclairée...Un jugement n’a de valeur morale que s’il
a de la valeur logique: s’il ne’st pas appuyé à des preuves, il est presque
nécessairement la cause d’une injustice...Il n’y a donc pas de probité morale
distincte de la probité scientifique: toute action reposant sur un jugement, la
méthode qui sert à établir des jugements exacts peut déterminer les actions
bonnes...la morale n’est pas seulement affaire de conscience, mais affaire de
science...une conscience dénuée d’esprit scientifique peut devenir criminelle”
(269). With that last line, especially, Lapie offers the precise opposite of
the more typically 20th century judgment that science without
conscience easily (inevitably) becomes criminal.
Lapie wants to retain the idea of collective action and
morality—that is, political choice and commitment—but without the pernicious
form of collective responsibility that holds an individual responsible for the
supposed crimes of, say, the race, family, nation, and so forth. In a curious
turn of phrase, Lapie writes “Toute notre étude est destinée à montrer que nous
sommes tous responsables de la crise qui vient d’éclater” (270). I take this to
mean that the study he is now winding up shows that the present crisis has
roots in collective conscience, in various collective and institutional
failures for which we are all, in a certain way, responsible. Because, he goes
on to say, we aren’t all equally responsible. Those who have simply failed to
conquer their outmoded prejudices, who have failed to reform institutions as justice
demands, that is the vast majority, are partly to blame, “mais quelques hommes,
qui ont joué un rôle important dans l’affaire, encourent une responsabilité
plus directe” (270).
In sum, for Lapie, the current crisis—the affair, not yet
capitalized—has to do with our failure to fully assume the moral consequences of the scientific revolution. Systematic doubt
is difficult, and so we prefer not to practice it. But if justice is to be our
ordering principle, then we must prefer truth to opinion or mere conscience. Lapie wraps things up
neatly, invoking in his closing paragraph the difference between authorship of
an act and the various grades of responsibility and social consequence, as well
as closing with the same mot from
Tostoy (or, Tolstoï)—“il est très bon qu’un cas de conscience se pose pour la
France”—good indeed, Lapie says, if we meet the challenge not with simple
reaction, but with measured self-criticism and improvement of “nos institutions
et de nos esprits” (271).
How to interpret this text, and the appeal it had for the Union? It is, most obviously, a text in
favor of revision of the verdict against Dreyfus. Lapie argues powerfully
against the injustice built into military courts, and is clear that truth,
pursued in a scientific way—and here is an argument for a certain style of republican
professor—must be the overriding value. That truth and justice are coincident
he feels he may simply assert. The ‘instinctive kantism’ remark is interesting
in light of the neo-Kantianism that pervaded the Rmm, but Lapie himself—as many others—was as much a Platonist as
anything else (although what that means is a difficult question). Much that
Lapie says appears today almost laughably naive, and surely one must quickly
ask after who, exactly, is in a position to enunciate the truth of which he speaks.
And yet.
The desire for a public that is institutionally committed to
methodical doubt, to the pursuit of justice through that of truth—this is
appealing. And further there is something appealing about the round rejection
of conscience-claims. This sounds, on its face, flatly antiliberal. Freedom of
conscience is a fundamental freedom. But I don’t think this is quite what he
means. He means, rather, that because you feel something deeply does not mean
you have any kind of right to assert it as true. We can go one further and say
that since truth is intersubjective, this can be extended to mean that you do
not have a right to oblige others to accept what you feel deeply just because
you are “intimately convinced” of it. This is, as Lapie would doubtless be
happy to further explain, an Enlightenment point of view. There is no truth,
and so no justice, without ruthless critique. It would be easy to object to
this sort of position, for instance in its characterization of conscience, in
the necessary connection of truth and justice, or in how Lapie relates the
individual to the institutional. Indeed people Lapie knew well made such
objections to him at various points. He has, nonetheless, the merit—more rare
than one might think—of writing with great conviction about the need to temper
conviction with evidence and doubt.
Wednesday, April 29, 2015
What was liberalism?
Duncan Bell. “What is Liberalism?” Political Theory 42(6), 682-715, 2014.
It is tempting to regard liberalism as a ‘sick signifier,’
a term that may now have polemical value in certain situations, but the meaning of which is so poorly determined
as to make use counter-productive. A
temptation, I think, worth resisting. Bell’s useful article attempts an answer
to its titular question, although the author believes that his material “calls into question the general
utility of “liberalism” as a category of political analysis” (705). Bell
restricts his investigation mostly to the British, and (almost—more on that
below) entirely to the Anglophone, political fields. He begins with the
observation, drawing on David Scott, that today we are all “conscripts of
liberalism,” meaning that “the
scope of the [liberal] tradition has expanded to encompass the vast majority of
political positions regarded as legitimate” (689). How to respond to
this over-inflation of the concept?
Acknowledging that one’s definition of a concept
(especially a political one) will depend on what one is trying to do, Bell writes, “I propose the
following definition (for comprehensive
purposes): the liberal tradition is constituted by the sum of the arguments that have been classified as liberal, and
recognised as such by other self-proclaimed liberals, across time and space”
(689-690). This technique accomplishes several things. It restricts us, first,
to the 19th century. Second, it is a way of accounting at least
partially for the polemical uses of the term. Third, it is important that
history, in the sense of conceptual continuity and change, is built into this
approach. Traditions can only be, as Bell writes, “constituted by the
accumulation of arguments over time”
(691). Bell has sensible things to say about the difficulties of adjudicating
at the edges of this, as well as about the importance of differentiating
between liberal speakers and liberal arguments.
The historical content of Bell’s argument—although the
article is rich and many of its notes are ones I should follow up—is easily
summed up. In the 19th century, liberalism was not among the most
important of political terms. Together with socialism and conservatism, it was
taken to be a product of the ‘era of revolutions’—the French especially—and to
be broadly synonymous with democracy. So, Bell gives us James Fitzjames Stephen
in 1862: “As generally
used . . . “liberal” and “liberalism” . . . denote in politics, and to some extent in literature and
philosophy, the party which wishes to alter existing institutions with the view of increasing popular
power. In short, they are
not greatly remote in meaning from the words “democracy” and “democratic.”” (694).
John Locke appeared essentially nowhere in these discussions. Herbert Spencer,
the enormously popular social scientist and surely a liberal, mentions Locke
hardly at all.
Today, we are all sure that Locke is, perhaps not the very
beginning of liberalism, but its defining thinker. Bell argues that “Locke became a liberal during the twentieth
century” (698). Beginning at the end of the 19th century, but
especially during the “crisis of liberalism” and its utter failure in the
1930s, scholars pushed the origins of liberalism back into the early modern
period. Bell makes this “retrojection” the first chronological and discursive
element constituting the new, hegemonic, idea of liberalism. The second and
more important, beginning during the 1930s and accelerating through the war,
was “the emergence and proliferation of the idea of “liberal democracy.” As representative forms of
political order came under sustained fire, intellectuals propagated an
all-encompassing narrative that simultaneously pushed the
historical
origins of liberalism back in time while vastly expanding its spatial reach.
For the first time, it was widely presented as either the most authentic
ideological tradition of the West (a pre-1945 storyline) or its constitutive
ideology (a view popular after 1945)” (699). In this new postwar
dispensation, liberalism was “centered on individual freedom in the context of
constitutional government” (699). And this was really a postwar understanding,
one which Bell signals as defined by complex disciplinary histories in “the
context of a transfer of scholarly authority from Britain to the United States”
(701). “As a global
conflict over the proper meaning of democracy raged, the modifier “liberal”
simultaneously encompassed diverse representative parliamentary systems while
differentiating them from others claiming the democratic title, above all
Italy, Germany, and the Soviet Union” (703). In short, Lockean
liberalism, which is the historical story underpinning the combat concept of
‘liberal democracy,’ are Cold War anti-totalitarian relics still exerting
unreasonable influence particularly in political theory departments.
Bell’s article is, as I’ve said, rich and valuable. I wish
I’d read it some time ago. The story is not a surprising one for me, although I
am not especially familiar with the British context on which he focuses. I’ve
already cited his point that the transformation he describes is defined by a
transfer of scholarly ‘weight’ from Britain to the US. He also mentions the
importance of émigré scholars in building the history of ideas as a discipline
in the US. (As an aside, I hadn’t realized that the Journal of the History of Ideas took CIA money), as well as the
translation from Italian of Guido De Ruggiero’s fascist-era History of European Liberalism. Now, I
have sympathy with the need to make linguistic and even national restrictions
for practical reasons, and even for certain methodological ones. But it seems
to m pretty clear—and of course Bell wouldn’t deny this—that the larger story
here is a European or larger one.
This moves in two directions. The first is that, it seems
to me, we would get very different responses depending on which national or
linguistic tradition we started with. For instance in Germany, I think the
postwar would find us looking not back to Locke, but perhaps back to Protestant
theology of one kind or another. This would not be a liberalism of property,
but one of personality (although equally anticommunist). In France we would see
a very different sequence. We would not find the consolidation of ‘liberal
democracy’ in the 1930s-50s. We would see a ‘liberal republicanism’ well before
the First World War, which might look back to 1789, although also further back,
and which would balance democratic claims with claims to fundamental individual
rights (as in the Declaration of the
Rights of Man and Citizen) in a way not so different from ‘liberal
democracy.’ The second is that, as I continue to think, the international
sphere is more than the sum of its parts. (I would hate to have to say
precisely how). All of this, moreover, leaves aside arguments about the essentially imperial origins of modern
liberalism (for instance, at least as I understand it, in Andrew Sartori’s most
recent book, which I haven’t yet read).
Tuesday, April 28, 2015
SFHS 2015. Part Two of Two.
Here is the promised second post on the SFHS. I’ve delayed
long enough that these papers aren’t really fresh in my mind any longer, but I
want to get this off my plate. Apologies for any misrepresentations! I’ll say
only that these papers deserve a more thoroughgoing treatment than I’m able to
give them here.
Saturday morning, at a little after 8:30, the panel “Beyond
Determinism: Rethinking the Philosophy of History and Political Economy in
Postwar France” got underway. Presenters included, in order, Daniel Steinmetz-Jenkins,
Alexander Arnold, and Aner Barzilay, with comment from Michael Behrent. All
three papers were excellent and, at least for me, educational. Behrent’s
comment was exemplary—at least what I heard of it. Since I had to leave part
way through I won’t have anything to say about it here.
Daniel Steinmetz-Jenkins (hereafter: DSJ) delivered a paper
on Raymond Aron entitled (I think) “Liberal Dictatorship, Aron’s Critique of
Hayek’s Concept of Liberty,” drawn from his dissertation in progress on Aron.
DSJ framed his project broadly as rescuing Aron from the historiographical box
of ‘lonely liberal critic of Marxism.’ Aron was more than just a critic of
Marxism, and engaged in a fruitful way with many different intellectuals (as it
happens I posted some notes on one of DSJ’s earlier papers about Aron and
Schmitt here). In particular, Aron leveled his critical fire at various forms
of ideology that found material support in the United States—development
theory, realist IR, etc—that made universalizing claims something like Marxism.
DSJ’s goal in this particular paper is to argue against the understanding of
Aron as a neo-liberal, as someone who walked the now-famous road to Mont Pelerin,
who was influenced by Hayek especially after a wartime stay in London. It isn’t
so, DSJ says.
DSJ develops his critique of the neo-liberal Aron first by
criticizing or “mitigating” the moment of sociability, the networks, that have
been pointed to in linking Aron to neo-liberalism. The heart of the paper,
though, is an archival record of a talk Aron gave in 1955 at a conference in
Milan (sponsored by the CCF, and in their archive). The context of this talk
was Aron’s new prominence as the author of The
Opium of the Intellectuals and especially the “end of ideology” thesis
found in its last chapter. This is great material, and DSJ contextualizes the debate in an exemplary
way—this, really, is the paper. The point for DSJ’s larger argument is that
Aron describes Hayekian liberalism as ideological in the same way as
Marxism—indeed he apparently said there that “at the end of the day, what the
liberalism of Hayek constitutes is inverted Marxism.” Economic inevitability
ruled both vision of the future, although they pointed in different directions.
Hayek would require, as in the title of the talk, a “liberal dictator” to get
his system off the ground. Well, Rousseau needed his legislator, so perhaps
this isn’t so unreasonable. I’d be interested, in light of this discussion, to
go back and re-read Aron’s “États democratiques et états totalitaires” (June
1939).
As is sometimes the case with this sort of argument, by the
end I wondered how anyone could possibly have ever thought of Aron as a
neoliberal. Perhaps this was clarified in the Q&A. My guess would be that
this label is as much an artifact of the polemical theater of French
intellectual politics as anything else. DSJ did not spend very much time
establishing the definition of neoliberalism according to which Aron would be
one, and it seems to me that in fact Aron was a liberal, not a neoliberal. DSJ
makes the case (I think convincingly) that a key difference between him and
Hayek was that the latter never really accepted the legitimacy of democracy,
while Aron did. Having spent some time reading Élie Halévy, Aron now sounds to
me more and more like his student, or, conversely, as though Halévy really was
Aron’s maître-penseur. The talk
mentioned above was, after all, delivered on the heels of an extremely
pessimistic survey of the field by Halévy. Perhaps we can say that Aron’s
liberalism was, at first, anti-totalitarian, but that he learned to shed this
fear as Hayek did not? In any case, a great presentation from DSJ.
Next up was Alexander Arnold, whose dissertation concerns
postwar (up to 80s) French political economy, and who spoke about Rosanvallon
and economic determinism. This paper was also great, the product of lots of
reading of Rosanvallon. I myself make use of Rosanvallon’s work, but I read him
first as a historian (the book on Guizot, for instance)—so this paper was
particularly interesting for me. Essentially, Arnold reconstructs Rosanvallon’s
political economy as he developed it over the course of the 1970s, in his
writings as an autogestionnaire. An
important climax is the critique of Marx offered in Le capitalisme utopique. I’m not certain that I’m reconstructing
Arnold’s reading correctly here, but the idea seems to be that Rosanvallon
believes we should read classical political economy as philosophy, not really
as a description of economic reality. At its base is an utopique description of the subject, for instance. Nonetheless,
Adam Smith—and here, can this really be what Rosanvallon thinks? It’s been some
time since I looked at that book—allows us for the first time to
philosophically grasp both the institution and the continuity of society. But
this is not a description of the world. Marx, however, took the writings of
liberal political economy for such a description, and his critique is
principally a critique of that economic (in fact philosophical) writing, not of
the real economy. “There is enormous distance between concrete society and the
discourse of political economy.” Capitalism, in reality, should be understood
in a minimal way, which allows for the construction of democratic—autogestionnaire—alternatives, or really
reforms.
This account of political economy, Arnold argues, or really
this inattention to it, left Rosanvallon and the deuxième gauche more generally unprepared to meet the challenges of
austerity that emerged in the Mitterand years. My central question here is not
so much about the reconstruction of Rosanvallon—although I would be interested
to see this story extended into his much deeper engagement with the French
liberal tradition as the 80s wore on—but about this ‘response.’ Who has been able to meet these challenges?
As far as I can tell no one really offers a really compelling account of what is to be done (at least no one who
isn’t on the side of austerity). The best Marxisant analyses I’ve seen are
rather grim. So what does Arnold want Rosanvallon to have done? To have
occupied a more intransigent oppositional position? I’m not sure. In any case,
to have avoided advocating “d’apprentissage collectif d’austérité...”
I’m leaving out here a number of things: especially Arnold’s
nuanced discussion of the merits of Rosanvallon’s self-description of autogestion as ‘realist,’ and Daniel
Lindberg’s criticisms of this; and then the larger framing of the paper in the
history of liberalism, and adjudication between the political and the economic
aspects of this. I look forward to reading more.
Finally, there was Aner Barzilay, whose talk was “Foucault
and Deleuze’s Hidden Debate about Nietzsche” [paraphrase!], and whose
dissertation is on Foucault’s Nietzsche. The larger project is to emphasize the
continuities on the level of philosophy in Foucault’s oeuvre. This is in
reaction to an over-emphasis on the late lectures and on Foucault as a theorist
of something called ‘neoliberalism.’ The larger context is above all the
question of the transcendental and the subject—trying to keep the two apart.
Nietzsche is the most important reference for Foucault, the actuator of the
whole project. Barsilay’s talk here is a reconstruction of a (largely implied)
dialogue between Foucault and Deleuze, and it is built around Barzilay’s archival
discovery of a 1977 note from Deleuze to Foucault discussing just these issues.
The exchange and the moment are fascinating. This period, and the political
break between the two philosophers, has now received a certain amount of
attention. So it is remarkable and much to be appreciated that Barzilay can
still bring something new to that table.
I cannot do justice to Barzilay’s talk, so I won’t try to
report its details. Delicate questions regarding the nature of the
transcendental, the plaisir/desire distinction, and power as Kantian
schematization of the subject, were all dissected. Neither Deleuze nor Foucault
is to be taken lightly, and Barzilay approaches at a level of textual
involvement but also abstraction that makes summary difficult. Again, I’d like
to read.
I agree broadly that we should take Foucault’s earlier work
more seriously when thinking about the later lectures. The problem of the
subject—historical, transcendental, prison, etc—is indeed clearly a central one
for Foucault (and the career-long circling around Kant is unsurprising). I’m
less convinced by the centrality of Nietzsche for Foucault generally, but I
think this is mostly because I’m skeptical that there’s much of a ‘there’—what
did Nietzsche mean, really? To what extent did Foucault take what he needed to
take from this corpus? The reference seems constantly to be to the Genealogy, which isn’t the same thing as
Nietzsche. But, after all, the point of the larger project is presumably to
argue this point. My larger concern with the paper is, I’m sure, not really
justified, but here it goes. This paper is, almost, saying: ‘hey, I know you
think that the late Foucault is about investigating the actual conditions in
which living human beings are made to suffer, but no, in fact it’s about the
far more important question of avoiding the transcendental subject!’ I
suppose what I want from Barzilay is an account of how the political thought of
this newly continuous philosopher-Foucault looks different, or should be
appreciated differently, from the less-continuous version of Foucault against
which Barzilay is arguing.
I think this is a legitimate question (despite everything)
because all three of these papers were about attempts to grapple with the
nature of the State. [I'd have liked, also, to hear more explicitly about the question of determinism--although perhaps the originally-planned fourth paper would have helped with this focus]. This common problem was of course clear. Barzilay mentioned, at the end
of his talk—and I’ve lost track of in precisely what register, and would like to know—that to refer to
the state is to bring a knife to the gunfight of modern politics. There is also Foucault’s famous remark from the lectures about cutting off the head of the
State, as well as that of the King. But at issue between Aron and Hayek was
interpretation of the nature of the State; and Rosanvallon’s political economy
seems also to have turned on the capacity of a subject—a State? A syndicat?—to intervene in the economy.
Now, this was self-consciously a panel of intellectual historians, so it is a
little pedantic to call on them to be more contextual. And probably Michael
Behrent did (some version of) that in his comment. Certainly his work on Foucault
and the Foucaultians makes me think him likely to have done so. But how to
create this context? Here the panel turns back on itself—intellectual history
often does—because, I think, the central question is how we, here today,
understand the changing nature of state power in the face of economic imperatives
in the postwar world. This is after all the problem all the subjects discussed
by the panel were interested in.
That closing is not too coherent, and not too clear, but
perhaps I’ll manage to follow it up with an eventual post on essays from the
no-longer-so-new Rethinking Modern
European Intellectual History (2014).
Monday, April 20, 2015
SFHS 2015. Part One of Two.
This past weekend was the meeting of the Society for French Historical Studies at Colorado College. I saw a number of excellent papers and
some quite cohesive panels. I’m going to do brief write-ups of only two of
these panels. The first, here, is a panel titled “Education, Religion,
and Laïcité in Republican France,” with papers by Linda Clark, Eleanor Rivera,
and Rachel Hutchins.
Linda Clark—“Women Educators and the
Politics of Laïcité: Normal School Directrices, 1879-1889”—spoke about the directrices of écoles normales for women
in the first decade after the institution of generalized secondary education
for women. In this period, there were approximately 180 such directrices (Clark has the exact number,
but I missed it). A few écoles normales already existed, of course, but a large
number of new women were needed to run the new schools that would be created
under the law. Eventually, although not at first, these women would be trained
at the new ENS at Fontenay-aux-Rose. Clark opened her talk with a letter sent
by an archbishop to Jules Ferry in 1880. Did Ferry know, the archbishop asked,
that one of his directrices was a
Protestant? Ferry replied that he did, but that her religion was not important,
only her professional capacity. Clark is broadly interested in this question:
how laïque were these early teachers?
Who were they? Clark’s paper was rich with valuable detail about this
all-important group. After all, if the schools were the heart of the republican
project, and the republic could survive only if it ‘won the battle’ for women,
then this group—those who would run the schools to teach the teachers—was of
great importance.
Clark divides her subjects into three
groups. There were 17 normal schools for women in France when the new law went
into effect in 1879. 10 had laïque directrices, and all these were retained as
new schools were opened. This is the first group. Second are the 33 directrices
appointed to newly-created schools mostly in the first year (79-80), who did
not pass through Fontenay-aux-Rose. Third is the remaining majority, women who
passed through the ENS at Fontenay and thus received the laique training that
was, ideally, supposed to prepare them for their task.
Clark’s paper showed that, at first,
Ferry and co. had to rely on more Catholic teachers, and allowed much greater
latitude for the expression of Catholic doctrine on the part of these directrices. In fact, especially in the
early years, Catholic directrices sometimes met with more success in effective
laicization than did non-Catholics. There was great turnover in the first few
years. This depended in part on regional differences, with more turnover in
more Catholic areas. Vendé saw four different directrices in four years. Mostly
these women were not married. The directrice had to live in the school, so some
people thought they should not be
married, or perhaps that it wasn’t a good idea to have husbands in the “couvent
laïque.” On the other hand there are several examples of married women as
directrice causing no particular difficulty or scandal. Republicans were in principle committed to
tolerance, so they noticed but accepted Catholic directrices as long as this
didn’t disrupt or obstruct laicization. Religious practices on the part of
directrices could be cause for dismissal—often
were, although sheer incompetence was as well—but there are also cases of
directrices being accused, and then defended successfully. Perhaps
surprisingly, complaints came both against too radically laïque directrices and against those who were not laïque
enough. By the late 1880s, there was less tolerance for Catholics. Once the ENS
at Fontenay is running, dismissals because of excessive Catholicism drop off
sharply. Only 1 of the 81 who went through was, ultimately, dismissed for
catholic practices.
My central take-away here was that, indeed, these
directrices were an effectively laïque bunch. Compromises were made, especially
at first, but the larger picture is of a surprisingly effective construction of
a corps of elite teachers.
Eleanor Rivera’s paper, “Neutral Space:
Laïcité and Early Third Republic Classrooms,” also examined the
contested edges, we might say, of Ferry-era laicization efforts, but in a quite
different mode. She uses the optic of space
to inquire about how laicization worked at the level of the primary school,
focusing on the Seine-inférieure. In fact what this means is a close look at
very local conflicts over the signs and symbols of religion mostly within
classrooms—especially crucifixes. I wonder, then, if Rivera’s framing might be
different: perhaps it is not so much space as material or visual traces of
religion that interests her? Or perhaps I’m over-remembering the spatial
framing of her paper?
However that may be, the paper itself was a fascinating and
detailed recounting of several such conflicts. Although at a different level of
the French educational systems than Clark, Rivera’s paper also demonstrated the
great variations according to local response that characterized efforts at
laicization—and, concomitantly, the flexibility in many cases of the higher
administration. Even after it became illegal to have crucifixes up in
classrooms, many remained when local conditions made it difficult for the
administration to have them removed without great conflict. Guidelines existed,
Rivera tells us, for when and how local teachers might best take these symbols
down (over a long break, quietly, quickly, and decisively). Conflicts
nonetheless arose. Rivera recounted in some detail one particular sequence in
which a local mayor declared his complete legitimacy—given by universal
suffrage—in attempting to re-install a crucifix removed from a classroom in his
town. This is interesting partly because the election of mayors was an
innovation on the part of the Third Republic, and so we see here a nice
dialectic of democratic legitimacy being accepted by opponents of republican
policies. The broader point of Rivera’s research (at least this part of it) was
that especially in primary education, teachers and administrators were willing
to retain a substantial amount of Catholic paraphernalia in and around the
classroom if it meant they could get the children into the school, and they could still control the curriculum.
Rachel Hutchins’ paper took us out of the early Third
Republic and into the (late?!) Fifth Republic. She is interested in the uses of
the term “laïcité” since 1980 in French primary school curriculum and textbooks
(which are importantly different). Hutchins’ paper, too, was rich with detail
and impressed upon me how little I know about recent French pedagogical
debates. For instance, in the early 1980s official policy removed ‘histoire’
from the curriculum, replacing it, on the basis of reasoning drawn from Piaget
and Annales historians, with direct interaction with artifacts and historical
documents, but without significant framing? If this is even partly right, I’d
be interested to know more.
In any case, Hutchins’ central argument is that, especially
in the textbooks that schoolchildren actually use, laïcité has undergone a
process of idealization. It has been transformed, in Hutchins’ excellent
phrase, “from value to myth.” She shows the differences between the official
position taken in the preambles to various curricular documents and the actual
content of the textbooks, which are not legally required to fit in any
particular way with official curricula. An important turning-point, she argues,
came as around 1985 national history returned to primary school curricula. At
first, in textbooks from the late 1980s, laïcité is mentioned only briefly, if
at all. By 2008, however, the main textbook for primary use on civil education
gives exactly as much space to laïcité as to liberté, égalité, fraternité.
Despite space also given to explicitly anti-racist messages, this way of
presenting the 1905 law in fact re-enforces, and this last is a paraphrase of
Hutchins, traditional nationalism in the guise of republican universalism.
Hutchins even shows that Islam is handled in history textbooks so as to
emphasize its warlike, conquest-oriented aspects. The crusades appear as a
‘reconquest’ on the part of Christian rulers. Muslims were commercial and
scientific in the past, but not, these textbooks suggest, in the present. This
part of Hutchins’ paper was very interesting, but I would have liked to see it
treated in a broader way—not something, of course, there was time for in the
paper.
A number of useful questions emerged from the audience.
(There was a very substantial comment from Barry Bergin, but for some reason my
notes from it are missing, so I won’t try to reconstruct it—suffice it to say
that he raised several of the below points as well). Hutchins, for instance,
who had framed the curricular changes she describes largely in terms of
xenophobic or anti-immigrant discourse and the rise of the FN, was asked about
other possible relevant changes. These are indeed numerous and not to be
discounted in post 1968 France. Jean Pedersen asked two (related!) questions of
the panel as a whole, which I shall mangle in paraphrasing. First, what is
really the continuity or the difference between laïcité in 1880 and the same
term today? Second, the form taken by laïcité in all these papers is
subtractive (my word), that is it removed symbols or practices in order to
achieve ‘neutrality.’ What about an (American) positive or inclusive model of
neutrality? This last, for any number of reasons, was indeed never on the table
in France. In fact, Rivera told in response a nice anecdote about a newspaper
column in which this very specter was raised—a crucifix with a cross, a start
of David, a ‘head of Mohammad’ (!), the mason’s level, all together—as a
possible outcome of botched laicization. This appeared as an abomination in the
1880s. (And today it is left to Slavoj Zizek to become outraged (or at least
worked-up) about the “coexist” bumper-stickers made out of these symbols.)
Pedersen did not really get an answer to her first question—indeed it is a
difficult one.
Of course, laïcité even over the long-term has been the
object of an enormous amount of excellent scholarship in France. Jacqueline
Lalouette leaps to mind here. It seems to me that we would be well-served to
analytically separate republican anticlericalism, which has roots well before
the Revolution and which played such an important role in it, from laïcité,
which I would understand as a 19th century synthesis of
free-thinking and Protestant approaches to deconnecting organized or institutionalized religion from morality. It seems
pretty clear that in the late 19th century, in the run-up to 1905,
Protestants played a key role in laicization, and that, at least on its face,
there was nothing atheist (we might say) about laïcité. The default
understanding—the rhetorical frame in the present—seems to be that laicization
worked in the Third Republic, but isn’t working now, should be made to work
with the same moral energy and clarity that it had in the 1880s. Certainly the
papers in this panel suggest that Ferry’s project (not that it was only his)
was a remarkable one. But it seems clear that to really understand the laïque
schools of the 1880s, we need at least to begin with the educational policies
and politics of the Second Empire. We need to think about the significance of
the Paris Commune in shaping political possibilities (and fears) in the first
decades of what would become the Third Republic. Republicans were not simply
Enlighteners fighting obscurantist Catholics. They were also (even the more
staunchly democratic among them) property-owners fighting socialists. And then
if we want a bilan of the Republican
school system, we’d better think very hard about the 1930s and Vichy, in
particular the extent to which the latter had “Republican origins.” Hutchins’
characterization of laïcité in recent years as a “myth” rather than a “value”
of the republic seems, at least from my perspective, dead on. The place that
the concept—the administrative strategy—of laïcité had in the political
conjuncture of the early Third Republic made it a functional part of the Republic and gave it, it seems to me, a completely
different meaning than it has today. Laïcité may have been a genuine myth in the late 19th century, and today merely rhetorical cover.
All of which is a long-winded response to three great
papers, Bergin’s comment, and questions from the audience—as well, I should
say, as conversation after the panel. Having just written substantially more
about this than I meant to do, I’ll commit to doing the same (although at less
length) tomorrow with another, quite different panel: “Beyond Determinism:
Rethinking the Philosophy of History and Political Economy in Postwar France.”
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)