Thinking that it might be good to teach with, I recently
looked up the essay from which the phrase “usable past” is generally said to
come. The full title of the essay is, “On Creating a Usable Past,” it’s
centrally concerned with novels and poetry, and is by a literary critic or
literary historian, Van Wyck Brooks. I don’t expect to use it in an
undergraduate classroom. But it is interesting, and so here I’m going to point
out what I think is worth retaining from it. Also, I want to record some ideas
about the surprising (to me) essay that immediately follows Brooks in this same
issue – a labor organizer and activist named Helen Marot writing a brief for
what I would call syndicalist educational ideas. The April 11, 1918 number of The
Dial featured an impressive list of contributors. John Dewey leads the
issue, then comes Charles Beard, then Brooks, and finally Marot, who compared
to these other luminaries is basically unknown. This is a special issue on
education, and the comparison between American and German institutions is
arguably the through-line of the four texts, with Brooks something of an
outlier. So it is worth returning to also as an example of a moment, maybe not
unlike ours, when perhaps the relationship between intellectual life or
cultural activity and the institutions of higher education was very much in
question.
What is our
relationship to the past, and what ought it be? For Brooks, speaking mainly
about literary culture, the answer to these paired questions is that we
Americans have been robbed of our birthright – what should have been our
tradition – and that it is time to create, in the famous titular phrase of his
essay, “a usable past” in order to combat the emptiness that disables our literature.
No doubt the essay could be put into the broader context of early 20th
century readers of Nietzsche, of the debate around philosophical pragmatism,
and, on an even larger scale, arguments over objectivity in the decades around
1900. One might look for instance to Peter Novick’s That Noble Dream, although
Brooks, since he was not a professional historian, is not a figure of
particular interest to Novick. For now though, let us just replace questions with our own: a past that is usable
– usable for who and what?
Brooks opens with a distinction
between two kinds of anarchy: one that “fosters” and one that “prevents
growth.” Brooks does not himself come back to this former kind of anarchy, although
it’s worth thinking about what he means by it. The latter kind is “the sudden
unbottling of elements that have had no opportunity to develop freely in the
open.” In America there are no “inherited resources,” there has been no
“cumulative culture,” and so every individual who wishes to do creative work
feels that they must start from the very beginning, all alone. Bad anarchy,
then, is each individual responding to their particular conditions on their
own. This, clearly, is a somewhat artificial situation, and Brooks places the
blame very clearly on professors of literature and literary history who “have
placed a sort of Talmudic seal upon the American tradition.” They exhibit a
“pathological vindictiveness” toward those who are attempting to do creative
work. Nothing made today can be as good as what came before, can even enter
into conversation with it.
Whence this
hatred for creative work in the professoriate? It is because anyone who is
successful in American academic life – and again this is in 1918 – must have
fully accommodated themselves to “the exigencies of the commercial mind.” The
professor by default orients himself toward “the ideal not of the creative but
of the practical life.” The professor “passively plays into the hands that
underfeed his own imaginative life.” Finding his own fulfillment and meaning in
the closed and perfect past he tips the balance against “the living present,”
which, for his own psychological protection, he can only despise. Hence, says
Brooks, the histories of American literature that exist always treat the
present (starting around 1890) as a total failure, and “stumble and hesitate”
when it comes even to Whitman. Practicality means commercial life and is
antithetical to creative production; it is destructive of tradition. We may
note that usability for the novelist or poet is to be distinguished from the
practical.
The university has already been
conquered by the latter, indeed scholarship in a merely objective mode is the
deformation of intellectual life in the spirit of commercial practicality.
For the professorial
mind, as I have said, puts a gloss upon the past that renders it sterile for
the living mind. Instead of reflecting the creative impulse in American
history, it reaffirms the values established by the commercial tradition; it
crowns everything that has passed the censorship of the commercial and
moralistic mind. And it appears to be justified because, on the whole, only
those American writers who have passed that censorship have undergone a
reasonably complete development and in this way entered what is often
considered the purview of literary criticism.
And here Brooks makes an interesting claim: successful literature
thus far has been “chiefly a literature of exploitation, the counterpart of our
American life.” Following the literal exploitation of the frontier there is its
cultural exploitation (“Irving and Longfellow and Cooper and Bryant”). The very
exceptionality of Emerson, Thoreau, and Whitman proves the larger point.
Exploitation, however, lasts only so long. After the initial “unbottling,”
there is nothing substantial left, only “lachrymosity” and spectacle.
For particular writers, as we can
see from the sorry record, there are only episodes of success, no full
development of authorial character. And yet, “the spiritual welfare of this
country depends altogether upon the fate of its creative minds.” These creative
minds are in a catastrophic position: “We want bold ideas, and we have nuances.
We want courage, and we have universal fear. We want individuality, and we have
idiosyncrasy. We want vitality, and we have intellectualism. We want emblems of
desire, and we have Niagaras of emotionality. We want expansion of soul, and we
have an elephantiasis of the vocal organs. Why? Because we have no cultural
economy, no abiding sense of spiritual values, no body of critical
understanding? Of course.” And why? Because “the present is a void, and the
American writer floats in that void because the past that survives in the
common mind of the present is a past without living value.” The past ought to anchor, provide one with
some footing that would be secure enough to allow forward motion.
For Brooks, the Europeans are in a
much better situation. They have continuous tradition, livings pasts, literary
histories that allow new writers to pick up a project already begun. European
professors have “intellectual freedom” that does not exists in America. And
looking to Europe can help the American in other ways. First, they offer us the
example of created, invented, useful pasts. Carlyle and Michelet, for instance,
have made just that. But in America “the grey conventional mind casts its
shadow backward” and not much of use has been written by the historians. Second,
as even a little foreign travel (spiritual or physical) demonstrates, different
countries have different and differently useful ideas about each other. The
Italians, for instance, have a very different understanding of French history
than the British have, because these two nations need different things from it.
Similarly, the tradition of American literature appears in a new light when
seen from abroad. “Englishmen will ask you why we Americans have so neglected
Herman Melville…Russians will tell you that we never really understood the
temperament of Jack London.” Thus by leaving America, we can learn to ask
ourselves what really matters in it for us so that “the past experience
of our people can be placed at the service of the future.”
We begin to arrive here at Brooks’ positive
program for getting “a vital order out of the anarchy of the present” and
reconnecting the “warm artery that ought to lead from the present back into the
past,” which has been severed by the anarchic disdain of the professoriate. What
do we get if we focus our attention on the creative impulse as it has appeared
in American life? “What emerges them is the desire, the aspiration, the
struggle, the tentative endeavor, and the appalling obstacles our life has
placed before them.” We have the continual appearance of creative energies, and
their interruption by the practical. Again, “sudden unbottling” rather than
open development, has been the rule. This problem itself, Brooks suggests,
becomes the heart of a usable American history. One example is the thwarted
development of Theodore Dreiser. “And there is Vachel Lindsay,” who comes to
value sound and color alone because that’s what they like in small towns. So, for
Brooks, it is not individual works that ought to draw our attention, rather we
should seek “tendencies.” And this seems to mean to him mainly patterns of
failure in the trajectories of particular writers. “Why did Ambrose Bierce go
wrong?” Or Stephen Crane, or Herman Melville again. Brooks concludes thus:
“Knowing that others have desired the things we desire and have encountered the
same obstacles, and that in some degree time has begun to face those obstacles
down and make the way straight for us, would not the creative forces of this
country lose a little of the hectic individualism that keeps them from uniting
against their common enemies? And would this not bring about, for the first
time, that sense of brotherhood in effort and in aspiration which is the best
promise of a national culture?”
So for Brooks cultural or spiritual
life is defined not by particular texts, but by the development of authorial
personalities – styles, we might say. The national community in its capacity
for self-reflection is both the condition and the telos of literary production.
For it to develop, individuals must be able to develop themselves as
personalities within it. The university is not an aid to this, but is itself so
caught in the practical and exploitative life of the country – at least of
America – that it is an active enemy of intellectual or creative life. We must go
abroad in order to see ourselves and our own options more clearly. There is a
naturalness to the development of tradition (the “warm artery”) but also
clearly it can be created. At the moment, the universities are actively sabotaging
the construction of a national cumulative tradition, but the European example
suggests they could – were they free enough from the influence of commerce – help
in the good work.
We can see Nietzsche floating
around in the background here, as well perhaps as Turner’s famous argument
about the frontier and American character, and even the kinds of arguments that
Carl Becker would make in “Everyman his own Historian” about the usability and
living nature of the past. We should also not forget that this literary moment,
in retrospect, will belong to modernism. TS Eliot and Ezra Pound are only two
of the Americans who went to Europe in search of something very different from
the usable national past that Brooks seems to see on the horizon. So we could
read Eliot’s “Tradition and the Individual Talent” as a response here, although
perhaps it would be better to understand “Prufrock” as, already, offering a
radically different account of the relationship between past and present and
future.
I’ve gone on very long already, but
I want just to end by suggesting that Helen Marot’s text offers us, I think, a
different kind of critique. Who was Marot? She was a librarian and a labor
organizer. There’s a good deal to say about hergood deal to say about her, and one might start here, but for present
purposes it’s significant that she wrote in 1914 a book about the IWW and had a
stint on the editorial board of The Masses before it was shut down by
the US government in 1917. She joined The Dial shortly after.
Where Brooks cares mainly about
literature, Marot takes the industrial school as her object. Marot frames her
intervention in line with Dewey’s at the beginning of the issue – should the
United States attempt to adopt a German style of industrial education? – but
goes on to make an argument about the emancipatory possibilities of what might
otherwise be derisively referred to as industrial or vocational training. Like
Brooks, she presents us with a dichotomy, this time between predatory and
creative profit-making. Like Brooks, she wishes to save the future and foster
creative activity. Unlike Brooks, for Marot it is precisely within practical
life that this emancipation of creativity can happen. Also unlike Brooks, her project
is profoundly and essentially democratic rather than elitist.
German education has contributed to
making what she – and she says everyone – recognizes as an extraordinarily
efficient industrial plant. The workers are effective and docile. Yet this kind
of education, Marot says, does not fit the United States. “The German has no pressing sense of the need
to experiment with life” – here in the USA, we do. Marot presents an
alternative path forward for industrial schools which are, today, she says,
indeed not very effective. Her vision is a frankly syndicalist one: “No work in
the subject matter of industry is education which does not in intention or in
fact give the persons involved the ability to participate in the administration
of industry.” As things stand, industrial education does the opposite: “the
pupils gain more the sense of the power of the subject to control them, than an
experience in their power to master the subject.” This mastery, this capacity
to manage modern industrial production, is what Marot wants for every working
person.
We cannot give up modern industrial
production, there is no going back to an old craft system of production. The
division of labor, technological development – these are conditions that, we
should understand, in fact contain new possibilities. “Technological subject
matter…is not part of common experience” – at least not yet. It ought to be. “If
released for common experimentation, it is fit matter for making science a
vital experience in everyday life.” Educators ought to seize this opportunity
and “initiate produce enterprises wherein young people will be free to gain
first-hand experience in the problems of industry.” We must, this is to
say, fully embrace technological production as what we might call an element of
civilization.
The people to ally with here are
not so much the businessmen or financiers as people like architects and
especially “engineers, not under the influence of business, are qualified to
open up the creative aspects of production to the workers.” Marot cites Robert B. Wolf (on whom, see here),
speaking at the Taylor Society, as an inspiration here, who argued that
Scientific Management ought to bend its science to “making him [the working
man] self-reliant and creative.” That’s not what happens now, because
industrial education is carried on entirely from the side of business, and so
“turn industrial education into industrial training” Educators, on the other
hand, are positioned to bring out the “adventure” that exists in industry.
“Industrial problems carry those who participate in their solution into pure
and applied science, into the study of the market for raw materials and
finished products, into the search for unconquered wealth.” Their goal is
“to give young people, not an experience which is tagged on to industry under
the influence of profits, but an experience which is inspired by the desire to
produce and the opportunity to develop the inspiration.” Going a little
beyond what Marot has written, and thinking about Taylor’s own writings – we can
say that this is of course directly opposed to the plain meaning of Taylorism,
which sought precisely and explicitly to strip from the worker all his accumulated
store of knowledge and turn it over to the manager, to reduce to zero the ‘inspiration’
of the worker so as to achieve docile efficiency.
This is just what Marot is against.
The big industrialists and financiers may well attempt to impose German style
efficiency education in the USA. They’ll fail, but the cost will be high for
everyone. We shouldn’t let them try: “the problem for American educators is the
retention of our native concept of experimental life and the attainment of
standards of workmanship – the realization of the strength of associated
effort, together with the advance of wealth production.” What we need to do is
insist on, says Marot, is a creative rather than a predatory industrial
structure. Wealth exploitation must not be allowed to be synonymous with wealth
production. For the creative concept to win out, it must “rest upon a people’s
desire for productive experience, and their ability to associate together for
that common end.” What Marot is trying to do, this is to say, is link a
critique of shop floor and classroom practices with a larger critique of capitalist
accumulation.
I’ve called Marot’s line of
argument here syndicalist, and I was struck by how familiar some of it sounds from the French context. It fits to some degree with the populist mode of
thinking about education. However it is revolutionary because Marot sees
industrial education and education more broadly neither as training for the
shop floor nor as an engine of class mobility, but rather as enabling the
transformation of class relations themselves. Brooks had introduced a
distinction between the practical and the useful, Marot one between predatory
and creative wealth – both are supposed to mark a distance from a certain kind
of bad commercial exploitation. Both want to re-activate or make available the
past for use in the present, but for Brooks this is a basically elite project;
for Marot the technical aspect of production is to be separated from the
commercial one in order to render it – the adventure of scientific and
technological capacity – available for popular use. Marot wants, we could say, to
make of industrial production a usable past for all people.