This past weekend was the meeting of the Society for French Historical Studies at Colorado College. I saw a number of excellent papers and
some quite cohesive panels. I’m going to do brief write-ups of only two of
these panels. The first, here, is a panel titled “Education, Religion,
and Laïcité in Republican France,” with papers by Linda Clark, Eleanor Rivera,
and Rachel Hutchins.
Linda Clark—“Women Educators and the
Politics of Laïcité: Normal School Directrices, 1879-1889”—spoke about the directrices of écoles normales for women
in the first decade after the institution of generalized secondary education
for women. In this period, there were approximately 180 such directrices (Clark has the exact number,
but I missed it). A few écoles normales already existed, of course, but a large
number of new women were needed to run the new schools that would be created
under the law. Eventually, although not at first, these women would be trained
at the new ENS at Fontenay-aux-Rose. Clark opened her talk with a letter sent
by an archbishop to Jules Ferry in 1880. Did Ferry know, the archbishop asked,
that one of his directrices was a
Protestant? Ferry replied that he did, but that her religion was not important,
only her professional capacity. Clark is broadly interested in this question:
how laïque were these early teachers?
Who were they? Clark’s paper was rich with valuable detail about this
all-important group. After all, if the schools were the heart of the republican
project, and the republic could survive only if it ‘won the battle’ for women,
then this group—those who would run the schools to teach the teachers—was of
great importance.
Clark divides her subjects into three
groups. There were 17 normal schools for women in France when the new law went
into effect in 1879. 10 had laïque directrices, and all these were retained as
new schools were opened. This is the first group. Second are the 33 directrices
appointed to newly-created schools mostly in the first year (79-80), who did
not pass through Fontenay-aux-Rose. Third is the remaining majority, women who
passed through the ENS at Fontenay and thus received the laique training that
was, ideally, supposed to prepare them for their task.
Clark’s paper showed that, at first,
Ferry and co. had to rely on more Catholic teachers, and allowed much greater
latitude for the expression of Catholic doctrine on the part of these directrices. In fact, especially in the
early years, Catholic directrices sometimes met with more success in effective
laicization than did non-Catholics. There was great turnover in the first few
years. This depended in part on regional differences, with more turnover in
more Catholic areas. Vendé saw four different directrices in four years. Mostly
these women were not married. The directrice had to live in the school, so some
people thought they should not be
married, or perhaps that it wasn’t a good idea to have husbands in the “couvent
laïque.” On the other hand there are several examples of married women as
directrice causing no particular difficulty or scandal. Republicans were in principle committed to
tolerance, so they noticed but accepted Catholic directrices as long as this
didn’t disrupt or obstruct laicization. Religious practices on the part of
directrices could be cause for dismissal—often
were, although sheer incompetence was as well—but there are also cases of
directrices being accused, and then defended successfully. Perhaps
surprisingly, complaints came both against too radically laïque directrices and against those who were not laïque
enough. By the late 1880s, there was less tolerance for Catholics. Once the ENS
at Fontenay is running, dismissals because of excessive Catholicism drop off
sharply. Only 1 of the 81 who went through was, ultimately, dismissed for
catholic practices.
My central take-away here was that, indeed, these
directrices were an effectively laïque bunch. Compromises were made, especially
at first, but the larger picture is of a surprisingly effective construction of
a corps of elite teachers.
Eleanor Rivera’s paper, “Neutral Space:
Laïcité and Early Third Republic Classrooms,” also examined the
contested edges, we might say, of Ferry-era laicization efforts, but in a quite
different mode. She uses the optic of space
to inquire about how laicization worked at the level of the primary school,
focusing on the Seine-inférieure. In fact what this means is a close look at
very local conflicts over the signs and symbols of religion mostly within
classrooms—especially crucifixes. I wonder, then, if Rivera’s framing might be
different: perhaps it is not so much space as material or visual traces of
religion that interests her? Or perhaps I’m over-remembering the spatial
framing of her paper?
However that may be, the paper itself was a fascinating and
detailed recounting of several such conflicts. Although at a different level of
the French educational systems than Clark, Rivera’s paper also demonstrated the
great variations according to local response that characterized efforts at
laicization—and, concomitantly, the flexibility in many cases of the higher
administration. Even after it became illegal to have crucifixes up in
classrooms, many remained when local conditions made it difficult for the
administration to have them removed without great conflict. Guidelines existed,
Rivera tells us, for when and how local teachers might best take these symbols
down (over a long break, quietly, quickly, and decisively). Conflicts
nonetheless arose. Rivera recounted in some detail one particular sequence in
which a local mayor declared his complete legitimacy—given by universal
suffrage—in attempting to re-install a crucifix removed from a classroom in his
town. This is interesting partly because the election of mayors was an
innovation on the part of the Third Republic, and so we see here a nice
dialectic of democratic legitimacy being accepted by opponents of republican
policies. The broader point of Rivera’s research (at least this part of it) was
that especially in primary education, teachers and administrators were willing
to retain a substantial amount of Catholic paraphernalia in and around the
classroom if it meant they could get the children into the school, and they could still control the curriculum.
Rachel Hutchins’ paper took us out of the early Third
Republic and into the (late?!) Fifth Republic. She is interested in the uses of
the term “laïcité” since 1980 in French primary school curriculum and textbooks
(which are importantly different). Hutchins’ paper, too, was rich with detail
and impressed upon me how little I know about recent French pedagogical
debates. For instance, in the early 1980s official policy removed ‘histoire’
from the curriculum, replacing it, on the basis of reasoning drawn from Piaget
and Annales historians, with direct interaction with artifacts and historical
documents, but without significant framing? If this is even partly right, I’d
be interested to know more.
In any case, Hutchins’ central argument is that, especially
in the textbooks that schoolchildren actually use, laïcité has undergone a
process of idealization. It has been transformed, in Hutchins’ excellent
phrase, “from value to myth.” She shows the differences between the official
position taken in the preambles to various curricular documents and the actual
content of the textbooks, which are not legally required to fit in any
particular way with official curricula. An important turning-point, she argues,
came as around 1985 national history returned to primary school curricula. At
first, in textbooks from the late 1980s, laïcité is mentioned only briefly, if
at all. By 2008, however, the main textbook for primary use on civil education
gives exactly as much space to laïcité as to liberté, égalité, fraternité.
Despite space also given to explicitly anti-racist messages, this way of
presenting the 1905 law in fact re-enforces, and this last is a paraphrase of
Hutchins, traditional nationalism in the guise of republican universalism.
Hutchins even shows that Islam is handled in history textbooks so as to
emphasize its warlike, conquest-oriented aspects. The crusades appear as a
‘reconquest’ on the part of Christian rulers. Muslims were commercial and
scientific in the past, but not, these textbooks suggest, in the present. This
part of Hutchins’ paper was very interesting, but I would have liked to see it
treated in a broader way—not something, of course, there was time for in the
paper.
A number of useful questions emerged from the audience.
(There was a very substantial comment from Barry Bergin, but for some reason my
notes from it are missing, so I won’t try to reconstruct it—suffice it to say
that he raised several of the below points as well). Hutchins, for instance,
who had framed the curricular changes she describes largely in terms of
xenophobic or anti-immigrant discourse and the rise of the FN, was asked about
other possible relevant changes. These are indeed numerous and not to be
discounted in post 1968 France. Jean Pedersen asked two (related!) questions of
the panel as a whole, which I shall mangle in paraphrasing. First, what is
really the continuity or the difference between laïcité in 1880 and the same
term today? Second, the form taken by laïcité in all these papers is
subtractive (my word), that is it removed symbols or practices in order to
achieve ‘neutrality.’ What about an (American) positive or inclusive model of
neutrality? This last, for any number of reasons, was indeed never on the table
in France. In fact, Rivera told in response a nice anecdote about a newspaper
column in which this very specter was raised—a crucifix with a cross, a start
of David, a ‘head of Mohammad’ (!), the mason’s level, all together—as a
possible outcome of botched laicization. This appeared as an abomination in the
1880s. (And today it is left to Slavoj Zizek to become outraged (or at least
worked-up) about the “coexist” bumper-stickers made out of these symbols.)
Pedersen did not really get an answer to her first question—indeed it is a
difficult one.
Of course, laïcité even over the long-term has been the
object of an enormous amount of excellent scholarship in France. Jacqueline
Lalouette leaps to mind here. It seems to me that we would be well-served to
analytically separate republican anticlericalism, which has roots well before
the Revolution and which played such an important role in it, from laïcité,
which I would understand as a 19th century synthesis of
free-thinking and Protestant approaches to deconnecting organized or institutionalized religion from morality. It seems
pretty clear that in the late 19th century, in the run-up to 1905,
Protestants played a key role in laicization, and that, at least on its face,
there was nothing atheist (we might say) about laïcité. The default
understanding—the rhetorical frame in the present—seems to be that laicization
worked in the Third Republic, but isn’t working now, should be made to work
with the same moral energy and clarity that it had in the 1880s. Certainly the
papers in this panel suggest that Ferry’s project (not that it was only his)
was a remarkable one. But it seems clear that to really understand the laïque
schools of the 1880s, we need at least to begin with the educational policies
and politics of the Second Empire. We need to think about the significance of
the Paris Commune in shaping political possibilities (and fears) in the first
decades of what would become the Third Republic. Republicans were not simply
Enlighteners fighting obscurantist Catholics. They were also (even the more
staunchly democratic among them) property-owners fighting socialists. And then
if we want a bilan of the Republican
school system, we’d better think very hard about the 1930s and Vichy, in
particular the extent to which the latter had “Republican origins.” Hutchins’
characterization of laïcité in recent years as a “myth” rather than a “value”
of the republic seems, at least from my perspective, dead on. The place that
the concept—the administrative strategy—of laïcité had in the political
conjuncture of the early Third Republic made it a functional part of the Republic and gave it, it seems to me, a completely
different meaning than it has today. Laïcité may have been a genuine myth in the late 19th century, and today merely rhetorical cover.
All of which is a long-winded response to three great
papers, Bergin’s comment, and questions from the audience—as well, I should
say, as conversation after the panel. Having just written substantially more
about this than I meant to do, I’ll commit to doing the same (although at less
length) tomorrow with another, quite different panel: “Beyond Determinism:
Rethinking the Philosophy of History and Political Economy in Postwar France.”
No comments:
Post a Comment